[Home] [Headlines] [Latest Articles] [Latest Comments] [Post] [Sign-in] [Mail] [Setup] [Help]
Status: Not Logged In; Sign In
Science/Tech See other Science/Tech Articles Title: Kill Whitey. It’s the Right Thing to Do. By David Dobbs September 15, 2010 | 4:51 pm | Categories: Brains and Behavior, Neuron Culture, Science Blogs A couple years ago, David Pizarro, a young research psychologist at Cornell, brewed up a devious variation on the classic trolley problem. The trolley problem is that staple of moral psychology studies at dinner parties in which you ask someone to decide under what conditions its morally permissible to kill one person to save others. Here, via Wikipedia, is its most basic template: This has generated scores of studies that pose all kinds of variations. (You can take a version of the test yourself at Should You Kill the Fat Man?) Perhaps the richest has been the footbridge problem. The footbridge scenario puts the subject in a more active (hypothetical role): Youre on a footbridge over the trolley track, and next to you, leaning perilously over the rail to see what happens, stands a very large man a man large enough, in fact, to stop the train. Is it moral to push the guy over the rail to stop the train? Researchers generally use these scenarios to see whether people hold a) an absolutist or so-called deontological moral code or b) a utilitarian or consequentialist moral code. In an absolutist code, an acts morality virtually never depends on context or secondary consequences. A utilitarian code allows that an acts morality can depend on context and secondary consequences, such as whether taking one life can save two or three or a thousand. In most studies, people start out insisting they have absolute codes. But when researchers tweak the settings, many people decide its relative after all: Say the man is known to be dying, or was contemplating jumping off the bridge anyway and the passengers are all children and for some people, that makes it different. Or the guy is a murderer and the passengers nuns. In other scenarios the man might be slipping, and will fall and die if you dont grab him: Do you save him
even if it means all those kids will die? By tweaking these settings, researchers can squeeze an absolutist pretty hard, but they usually find a mix of absolutists and consequentialists. As a grad student, Pizarro liked trolleyology. Yet it struck him that these studies, in their targeting of an absolutist versus consequentialist spectrum, seemed to assume that most people would hold firm to their particular spots on that spectrum that individuals generally held a roughly consistent moral compass. The compass needle might wobble, but it would generally point in the same direction. Pizarro wasnt so sure. He suspected we might be more fickle. That perhaps we act first and scramble for morality afterward, or something along those lines, and that we choose our rule set according to how well it fits our desires. To test this, he and some colleagues devised some mischievous variations on the footbridge problem. They detail these in a recent paper (pdf download; web), and Pizarro recently described them more accessibly in at the recent Edge conference on morality. (The talk is on video, or you can download the audio.) As Pizarro describes, the variations are all of a piece: All explore how the political and racial prejudices and guilt of both liberals and conservatives might affect where they stand on the absolutist-consequentialist spectrum. Perhaps most revealing is what Pizarro calls the Kill Whitey study. This was a footbridge problem two variations on a footbridge problem in one, actually that the team presented to 238 California undergrads. The undergrads were of mixed race, ethnicity and political leanings. Before they faced the problem, 87 percent of them said they did not consider race or nationality a relevant factor in moral decisions. Here the papers (.pdf) description of the problem they faced: Half of the participants received a version of the scenario where the agent could choose to sacrifice an individual named Tyrone Payton to save 100 members of the New York Philharmonic, and the other half received a version where the agent could choose to sacrifice Chip Ellsworth III to save 100 members of the Harlem Jazz Orchestra. In both scenarios the individual decides to throw the person onto the trolley tracks Tyrone and Chip. Just in case youre missing what Pizarro is up to: So the guy on the bridge kills either Tyrone to save the New York Philharmonic or Chip to save the Harlem Jazz Orchestra. How, Pizarro asked the students, did they feel about that? Was sacrificing Chip/Tyrone to save the Jazz Orchestra/Philharmonic justified? Was it moral? Was it sometimes necessary to allow the death of one innocent to save others? Should we ever violate core principles, regardless of outcome? Is it sometimes necessary to allow the death of a few to promote a greater good? Turned out the racial identities did indeed, ah, color peoples judgments, but it colored them differently depending on their political bent. Pizarro, who describes himself as a person who would probably be graded a liberal on tests, roughly expected that liberals would be more consistent. Yet liberals proved just as prejudiced here as conservatives were, but in reverse: While self-described conservatives more readily accepted the sacrifice of Tyrone than they did killing Chip, the liberals were easier about seeing Chip sacrificed than Tyrone. But this was just college students. Perhaps they were morally mushier than most people. So the team went further afield. As Pizarro describes in the talk: If youre wondering whether this is just because conservatives are racistwell, it may well be that conservatives are more racist. But it appears in these studies that the effect is driven [primarily] by liberals saying that theyre more likely to agree with pushing the white man and [more likely to] disagree with pushing the black man. So we used to refer to this as the kill whitey study. They offered some other scenarios too, about collateral damage in military situations, for instance, and found similar differences: Conservatives accepted collateral damage more easily if the dead were Iraqis than if they were Americans, while liberals accepted civilian deaths more readily if the dead were Americans rather than Iraqis. What did this say about peoples morals? Not that they dont have any. It suggests that they had more than one set of morals, one more consequentialist than another, and choose to fit the situation. Again, from the talk: Or as Pizarro told me on the phone, The idea is not that people are or are not utilitarian; its that they will cite being utilitarian when it behooves them. People are arent using these principles and then applying them. They arrive at a judgment and seek a principle. So well tell a child on one day, as Pizarros parents told him, that ends should never justify means, then explain the next day that while it was horrible to bomb Hiroshima, it was morally acceptable because it shortened the war. We act and then cite whichever moral system fits best, the relative or the absolute. Pizarro says this isnt necessarily bad. Its just different. It means we draw not so much on consistent moral principles as on a moral toolbox. And if these studies show were not entirely consistent, they also show were at least determined really determined, perhaps, given the gyrations we go through to try to justify our actions with behaving morally. We may choose from a toolbox but the tools are clean. As Pizarro puts it at the end of his talk, Post Comment Private Reply Ignore Thread Top Page Up Full Thread Page Down Bottom/Latest
#1. To: Prefrontal Vortex (#0)
THROW THE FAT PIG OFF THE BRIDGE!
I want either less corruption or more opportunity to participate in it. Ashleigh Brilliant
You must be shiiting us. What garbage.
|
||
[Home]
[Headlines]
[Latest Articles]
[Latest Comments]
[Post]
[Sign-in]
[Mail]
[Setup]
[Help]
|