[Home] [Headlines] [Latest Articles] [Latest Comments] [Post] [Sign-in] [Mail] [Setup] [Help]
Status: Not Logged In; Sign In
Editorial See other Editorial Articles Title: Ayn Rand: The Virtue of Selfishness--How Does One Lead A Rational Life In An Irrational Society? How Does One Lead A Rational Life In An Irrational Society? Ayn Rand The Virtue of Selfishness 1962 I will confine my answer to a single, fundamental aspect of this question. I will name only one principle, the opposite of the idea which is so prevalent today and which is responsible for the spread of evil in the world. That principle is: One must never fail to pronounce a moral judgment. Nothing can corrupt and disintegrate a culture or a mans character as thoroughly as does the precept of moral agnosticism, the idea that one must never pass moral judgment on others, that one must be morally tolerant of anything, that the good consists of never distinguishing good from evil. It is obvious who profits and who loses by such a precept. It is not justice or equal treatment that you grant to men when you abstain equally from praising mens virtues and from condemning mens vices. When your impartial attitude declares, in effect, that neither the good nor the evil may expect anything from youwhom do you betray and whom do you encourage? But to pronounce a moral judgment is an enormous responsibility. To be a judge, one must possess an unimpeachable character; one need not be omniscient or infallible, and it is not an issue of errors of knowledge; one needs an un- breached integrity, that is, the absence of any indulgence in conscious, wilful evil. Just as a judge in a court of law may err, when the evidence is inconclusive, but may not evade the evidence available, nor accept bribes, nor allow any personal feeling, emotion, desire or fear to obstruct his minds judgment of the facts of realityso every rational person must maintain an equally strict and solemn integrity in the courtroom within his own mind, where the responsibility is more awesome than in a public tribunal, because he, the judge, is the only one to know when he has been impeached. There is, however, a court of appeal from ones judgments: objective reality. A judge puts himself on trial every time he pronounces a verdict. It is only in todays reign of amoral cynicism, subjectivism and hooliganism that men may imagine themselves free to utter any sort of irrational judgment and to suffer no consequences. But, in fact, a man is to be judged by the judgments he pronounces. The things which he condemns or extols exist in objective reality and are open to the independent appraisal of others. It is his own moral character and standards that he reveals, when he blames or praises. If he condemns America and extols Soviet Russiaor if he attacks businessmen and defends juvenile delinquentsor if he denounces a great work of art and praises trashit is the nature of his own soul that he confesses. It is their fear of this responsibility that prompts most people to adopt an attitude of indiscriminate moral neutrality. It is the fear best expressed in the precept: Judge no, that ye be not judged. But that precept, in fact, is an abdication of moral responsibility: it is a moral blank check one gives to others in exchange for a moral blank check one expects for oneself. There is no escape from the fact that men have to make choices; so long as men have to make choices, there is no escape from moral values; so long as moral values are at stake, no moral neutrality is possible. To abstain from condemning a torturer, is to become an accessory to the torture and murder of his victims. The moral principle to adopt in this issue, is: Judge, and be prepared to be judged. The opposite of moral neutrality is not a blind, arbitrary, self-righteous condemnation of any idea, action or person that does not fit ones mood, ones memorized slogans or ones snap judgment of the moment. Indiscriminate tolerance and indiscriminate condemnation are not two opposites: they are two variants of the same evasion. To declare that everybody is white or everybody is black or everybody is neither white nor black, but gray, is not a moral judgment, but an escape from the responsibility of moral judgment. To judge means: to evaluate a given concrete by reference to an abstract principle or standard. It is not an easy task; it is not a task that can be performed automatically by ones feelings, instincts or hunches. It is a task that requires the most precise, the most exacting, the most ruthlessly objective and rational process of thought. It is fairly easy to grasp abstract moral principles; it can be very difficult to apply them to a given situation, particularly when it involves the moral character of another person. When one pronounces moral judgment whether in praise or in blame, one must be prepared to answer Why? and to prove ones caseto oneself and to any rational inquirer. The policy of always pronouncing moral judgment does not mean that one must regard oneself as a missionary charged with the responsibility of saving everyones soulnor that one must give unsolicited moral appraisals to all those one meets. It means: (a) that one must know clearly, in full, verbally identified form, ones own moral evaluation of every person, issue and event with which one deals, and act accordingly; (b) that one must make ones moral evaluation known to others, when it is rationally appropriate to do so. This last means that one need not launch into unprovoked moral denunciations or debates, but that one must speak up in situations where silence can objectively be taken to mean agreement with or sanction of evil. When one deals with irrational persons, where argument is futile, a mere I dont agree with you is sufficient to negate any implication of moral sanction. When one deals with better people, a full statement of ones views may be morally required. But in no case and in no situation may one permit ones own values to be attacked or denounced, and keep silent. Moral values are the motive power of mans actions. By pronouncing moral judgment, one protects the clarity of ones own perception and the rationality of the course one chooses to pursue. It makes a difference whether one thinks that one is dealing with human errors of knowledge or with human evil. Observe how many people evade, rationalize and drive their minds into a state of blind stupor, in dread of discovering that those they deal withtheir loved ones or friends or business associates or political rulersare not merely mistaken, but evil. Observe that this dread leads them to sanction, to help and to spread the very evil whose existence they fear to acknowledge. If people did not indulge in such abject evasions as the claim that some contemptible liar means wellthat a mooching bum cant help itthat a juvenile delinquent needs lovethat a criminal doesnt know any betterthat a power-seeking politician is moved by patriotic concern over the public good that communists are merely agrarian reformersthe history of the past few decades, or centuries, would have been different. Ask yourself why totalitarian dictatorships find it necessary to pour money and effort into propaganda for their own helpless, chained, gagged slaves, who have no means of protest or defense. The answer is that even the humblest peasant or the lowest savage would rise in blind rebellion, were he to realize that he is being immolated, not to some incomprehensible noble purpose, but to plain, naked human evil. Observe also that moral neutrality necessitates a progressive sympathy for vice and a progressive antagonism to virtue. A man who struggles not to acknowledge that evil is evil, finds it interestingly dangerous to acknowledge that the good is the good. To him, a person of virtue is a threat that can topple all of his evasionsparticularly when an issue of justice is involved, which demands that he take sides. It is then that such formulas as Nobody is ever fully right or fully wrong and Who am I to judge? take their lethal effect. The man who begins by saying: There is some good in the worst of us, goes on to say: There is some bad in the best of usthen: Theres got to be some bad in the best of usand then: Its the best of us who make life difficultwhy dont they keep silent?who are they to judge? And then, on some gray, middle-aged morning, such a man realizes suddenly that he has betrayed all the values he had loved in his distant spring, and wonders how it happened, and slams his mind shut to the answer, by telling himself hastily that the fear he had felt in his worst, most shameful moments was right and that values of no chance in this world. An irrational society is a society of moral cowardsof men paralyzed by the loss of moral standards, principles and goals. But since men have to act, so long as they live, such a society is ready to be taken over by anyone willing to set its direction. The initiative can come from only two types of men: either from the man who is willing to assume the responsibility of asserting rational valuesor from the thug who is not troubled by questions of responsibility. No matter how hard the struggle, there is only one choice that a rational can make in the face of such an alternative. Share this: Stum
Post Comment Private Reply Ignore Thread Top Page Up Full Thread Page Down Bottom/Latest Begin Trace Mode for Comment # 4.
#1. To: Flintlock, christine, all (#0)
fuckin A
THE VIRTUE OF SELFISHNESS MORE Throughout history, man has been offered the following alternative: be moral through a life of sacrifice to othersor be selfish through a life of sacrificing others to oneself. In The Virtue of Selfishness, Ayn Rand blasts this as a false alternative, holding that a selfish, non-sacrificial way of life is both possible and necessary for man. The Virtue of Selfishness is a collection of essays presenting Ayn Rands radical moral code of rational selfishness and its opposition to the prevailing morality of altruismi.e., to the duty to sacrifice for the sake of others. In The Objectivist Ethics, Rand gives an outline of her code of rational selfishness, and of her argument establishing it as the only objective, fact- based moral code in human history. In the course of the essay, she raises and answers a fundamental and fascinating question: Why does one even need a morality? In essays including The Ethics of Emergencies, The Conflicts of Mens Interests, and Doesnt Life Require Compromise? she raises common ethical questions, shows how altruism has crippled peoples ability to approach them rationally, and explains how her moral code provides a solution to them. In Mans Rights and The Nature of Government she applies her ethics to formulate the basic principles of her political philosophy, while rejecting the altruistic doctrines of rights to health care, employment, etc. The Virtue of Selfishness is indispensable reading for anyone who wants to understand the crucial ethical issues at the root at so many of our cultural debates todaywho wants to understand the revolutionary ideas that guide the lives of Ayn Rands fictional heroeswho wants to lead an existence that is both moral and practicalwho wants to discover why, in the words of one of the heroes of Atlas Shrugged, the purpose of morality is to teach you, not to suffer and die, but to enjoy yourself and live. Table of Contents Introduction The Objectivist Ethics, Ayn Rand (1961) Mental Health versus Mysticism and Self-Sacrifice, Nathaniel Branden (1963) The Ethics of Emergencies, Ayn Rand (1963) The Conflicts of Mens Interests, Ayn Rand (1962) Isnt Everyone Selfish?, Nathaniel Branden (1962) The Psychology of Pleasure, Nathaniel Branden (1964) Doesnt Life Require Compromise?, Ayn Rand (1962) How Does One Lead a Rational Life in an Irrational Society?, Ayn Rand (1962) The Cult of Moral Grayness, Ayn Rand (1964) Collectivized Ethics, Ayn Rand (1963) The Monument Builders, Ayn Rand (1962) Mans Rights, Ayn Rand (1963) Collectivized Rights, Ayn Rand (1963) The Nature of Government, Ayn Rand (1963) Government Financing in a Free Society, Ayn Rand (1964) The Divine Right of Stagnation, Nathaniel Branden (1963) Racism, Ayn Rand (1963) Counterfeit Individualism, Nathaniel Branden (1962) The Argument from Intimidation, Ayn Rand (1964) Index
Oh, how many years ago I read those words. I was in my mid 20s and searching for answers. After having read "Fountainhead" I wanted to know about the author and "The Virtue of Selfishness" was recommended. Thereafter, I looked to earlier works that could perhaps better define the author of such work. I found "We the Living" at an old book store in San Diego. I have that book to this day. I must add, I am still "searching for answers", but accept easily that "the purpose of morality is to teach you, not to suffer and die, but to enjoy yourself and live. Genghis: Thanks for taking me back to a time well spent with the works of Rand.
no problem. pass it on! you might like this too.
There are no replies to Comment # 4. End Trace Mode for Comment # 4.
Top Page Up Full Thread Page Down Bottom/Latest |
||
[Home]
[Headlines]
[Latest Articles]
[Latest Comments]
[Post]
[Sign-in]
[Mail]
[Setup]
[Help]
|